User:Fastfission/HST
|
The History of Science and Technology is a field of history which examines the entire spectrum of human experience relating to science and technology, including the development of theories, change between theories, disciplinary and institutional history, and the cultural, economic, and political impacts of science and technology.
Contents |
General history of science and technology
- Timeline of scientific experiments
- Timeline of scientific discoveries
- Timeline of technological discoveries
- Timelines of Science and Technology
- Biography of inventors, explorers, and scientists
- List of scientists, List of engineers and List of inventors
- List of years in science
For information on the histories of the many specific subdivisions of science, and the development of individual scientific branches and theories, see the entry on science.
See also: Category:History of science for links to articles which are of special interest to the history of science.
The origins of the discipline
Though scholars and scientists had been chronicling the results of scientific endeavors for centuries (such as William Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences from 1837, and the popular and historical accounts which accompanied the scientific revolution of the 17th century), the development of the distinct academic discipline of the history of science and technology did not occur until the early 20th century, and was intimately bound to the changing role of science during the same time period. The history of science was once exclusively the domain of retired researchers -- former scientists whose days in the laboratory had expired but still with a hearty interest in the field -- and the rare specialist. However in the decades since the end of World War II the field has evolved into a full academic discipline, with graduate schools, research institutes, public and private patronage, peer-reviewed journals, and professional societies.
Outsiders are often amazed that such a seemingly specialized discipline exists (though just how "specialized" the subject is depends on how broadly a definition of science and technology one uses). However the study of the history of science has had great effects on the philosophy of science, conceptions of the role of science in society, and scientific policy.
The founding figure of the discipline in the United States was George Sarton, later the founding editor of the journal Isis. Sarton and his family fled Belgium after the German invasion in World War I, and after a brief stay in England, he arrived in the United States penniless and unemployed. Sarton began lecturing part-time at several academic institutions, and in 1916 began a two year appointment at Harvard University. When his appointment did not look like it would be renewed, he appealed to Robert S. Woodward, president of the Carnegie Institution of Washington, for patronage. Woodward gave Sarton a two year position and in 1920 extended it to a permanent tenured appointment as a Research Associate in the Institution's Department of History.
Though modern scholars do not usually share Sarton's motivations -- Sarton saw the history of science as the only genuine example of human progress -- the tools he left to the field, the journal Isis and the annual volume Osiris (both still in print today), provided the foundation of the discipline in the United States.
The Hessen thesis and the birth of externalism
Just as the 1930s were a seminal decade for the development of our modern understanding of science, they were a seminal decade for the history and historiography of science as well. While Sarton taught the first American doctoral students in the discipline, in Europe some of the most influential historians and philosophers of science were first coming into the picture, and the setting of the philosophical battle which is now known as "the Science Wars" was being set.
In 1931, the Second International Congress of the History of Science was convened in London. The papers delivered by the Soviet delegation, lead by N.I. Bukharin, quickly invigorated the discipline. Boris Hessen in particular delivered a paper entitled "The Social and Economic Roots of Newton's Principia," in which he asserted that Isaac Newton's most famous work was created to cater to the goals and desires of 17th century industry and economy. Hessen asserted that Newton's work was inspired by his economic status and context, that the Principia was little more than the solution of technical problems of the bourgeoisie.
Present scholarship has revealed that Hessen's motives were not completely academic. At that time in the Soviet Union, the work of Albert Einstein was under attack by Communist Party philosophers; being supposedly motivated by bourgeois values, it was "bourgeois science" and should henceforth be banned. (In many ways this attack was similar to the Deutsche Physik movement in Germany which occurred only a few years later.) Hessen's paper was a lobbying tactic: Party philosophers would not challenge the accuracy of Newton's theories, and to show them as being motivated by bourgeois concerns would, in Hessen's eyes, show that scientific validity could exist whatever the motivations were for undertaking it. However, there is little evidence that his paper had any effect in the internal Soviet philosophical battles over Einstein's work.
Despite its lack of effect in his home country, Hessen's thesis had a wide effect in Western historiography of science. Though Hessen’s work is now easily dismissed as "vulgar Marxism," its focus on the relationship between society and science was, in its time, seen as novel and inspiring. It was a challenge to the notion that the history of science was the history of individual genius in action, the dominant view at least since William Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences in 1837.
Few contemporary Western readers of Hessen took his paper at face value. His rigid connection between economy and knowledge was not accepted by a majority of historians. However, his assertion that a connection existed between the growth of knowledge and the art of war, and that ballistics played a central part of physics and Newton's world, was viewed with keen interest. In the shadow of the first war to employ chemical weapons, and as the war machines were again gearing up in preparation for another world war, the role between science, technology, and warfare was becoming more interesting to scholars and scientists. Previous views of science as separate from the mundane or vulgar aspects of practical life -- the disembodiment of the scientific mind from its context -- were becoming less attractive than a view that science and scientists were increasingly embedded in the world in which they worked.
This became reflective in the scholarship of the time as well, with dissertations written on such subjects as "Science and War in the Old Regime," which examined the ways in which military engineering influenced pre-Revolution French scientists.
This method of doing the history of science became known as externalism, looking at the manner in which science and scientists are affected, and guided by, their context and the world in which they exist. It is an approach which eschews the notion that the history of science is the development of pure thought over time, one idea leading to another in a contextual bubble which could exist at any place, at any time, if only given the right geniuses.
The contrast to this approach, the method of doing history of science which preceded externalism, became known as internalism. Internalist histories of science often focus on the rational reconstruction of scientific theories and showing the development of science as being a process taking place wholly within the scientific world.
In practice, the line between internalism and externalism can be incredibly fuzzy. Few historians then, or now, would insist that either of these approaches in their extremes paint a wholly complete picture, nor would it necessarily be possible to practice one fully over the other. However, at their heart they contain a basic question about the nature of science: what is the relationship between the producers and consumers of scientific knowledge? The answer to this question must, in some form, inform the method in which the history of science and technology is conducted; conversely, how the history of science and technology is conducted, and what it concludes, can inform the answer to the question. The question itself contains an entire host of philosophical questions: what is the nature of scientific truth? What does "objectivity" mean in a scientific context? How does change in scientific theories occur?
The historian/sociologist of science Robert K. Merton produced many famous works following Hessen's thesis, which can be seen as reactions to and refinements of Hessen's argument. In his work on science, technology, and society in the 17th century England, Merton sought to introduce an additional category -- Puritanism -- to explain the growth of science in this period. Merton worked to split Hessen's crude category of economics into smaller subcategories of influence, including transportation, mining, and military technique. Merton also tried to develop empirical, quantitative approaches to showing the influence of external factors on science. Despite these changes, Merton was quick to note his indebtedness to Hessen. Even with his emphasis on external factors, though, Merton differed from Hessen in his interpretation: Merton maintained that while researchers may be inspired and interested by problems which were suggested by extra-scientific factors, ultimately the researcher's interests were driven by "the internal history of the science in question." Merton attempted to delineate externalism and internalism along disciplinary boundaries, with context studied by the sociologist of science, and content by the historian.
Vannevar Bush and World War II
Thomas Kuhn and the 1960s
The Sokal Hoax and the Science Wars
The discipline today
in progress...
Disciplinary figures
- Historians of science and technology:
- Philosophers of science:
- Sociologists of science
- Research institutes:
- Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin
- Dibner Institute for the History of Science and Technology (http://dibinst.mit.edu), MIT
- Morris Fishbein Center for the History of Science and Medicine (http://social-sciences.uchicago.edu/fishbein/), University of Chicago
- Professional societies:
- History of Science Society (http://www.hssonline.org/)
- Society for the History of Technology (http://shot.press.jhu.edu/)
- American Association for the History of Medicine (http://www.histmed.org/)
- British Society for the History of Science (http://www.bshs.org.uk/)
- European Association for the Study of Science and Technology (http://www.easst.net/)
- Graduate programs:
- Office for History of Science (http://ohst.berkeley.edu), University of California, Berkeley
- Department of History of Science (http://www.fas.harvard.edu/~hsdept/), Harvard University
- History of Medicine and History of Science (http://info.med.yale.edu/histmed/), Yale University
- Program in Science, Technology, and Society (http://web.mit.edu/sts/), MIT
- History of Science, Medicine, and Technology (http://histsci.wisc.edu/), University of Wisconsin
- School of History, Technology, and Society (http://www.hts.gatech.edu/), Georgia Institute of Technology
- More available at the History of Science Society's "Guide to the Profession" (http://www.hssonline.org/guide/)
See also
- philosophy of science
- science studies (Science and Technology Studies)
- Subdisciplines:
References
- Michael Aaron Dennis, "Historiography of Science: An American Perspective," in John Krige and Dominique Pestre, eds., Science in the Twentieth Century, Amsterdam: Harwood, 1997, pp. 1-26.
- Loren R. Graham, "Soviet attitudes towards the social and historical study of science," in Science in Russia and the Soviet Union: A Short History, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 137-155.
- Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago, 1962 (third edn, 1996).